“Justice and Virtue: The Republic’s
Inquiry into Proper Difference”
By: Aryeh Kosman
At the beginning of the dialogue,
the Republic can be seen as an
investigation into the concept of justice, but as the book progresses the
conversation’s scope of interest seems to broaden in order to include the notion
of virtue. Kosman wrote this article in order to define the relationship
between justice and virtue and the implications those have on how readers
interpret the Republic.
Kosman begins with a simplified
answer to the relationship between justice and virtue: “justice is virtue” (117). So, by this answer, it is necessary to
understand virtue in order to understand justice. Virtue, in the context of the
Republic is “a quality that an entity
has that enables it to perform its function well, that is, to be itself
characteristically in a good fashion” (120). This definition is established
when Socrates refers to the virtue of dogs and horses, where the virtue of a
horse is that which makes any horse a good horse (335b). When considering
virtue in this light, as “a good state of character”, Kosman linked virtue with
moral philosophy posing an idea that a person seeking a virtuous life should
ponder and its answer according to Plato: “what kind of person I should or
shouldn’t become” with the answer being “a person properly disposed to act in
certain appropriate ways” (120-121). The idea of a person taking on a specific
role, that each individual has a role that is appropriate for themselves at an
individual level, is a key concept in the Republic
that ties in both the concepts of justice and virtue. This idea has the
potential to tie together a debated flaw in the Republic, where “the problem that Socrates addresses is set in
terms of a conception of justice understood as just action and just behavior,
whereas the account of justice that Socrates offers as an answer to that
problem concerns justice as a state of character, as a certain harmony of the
soul…the argument has missed the point unless we can show that he former
behavior entails the latter condition” (121), as Kosman tries to prove
throughout the article.
Once virtue is defined, the search
for the specific meaning of justice can begin, and for this purpose Kosman
poses the question of “which virtue specifically is justice?” because “justice is a virtue…it is one among the states or qualities of an entity that
in some sense enable that entity to do well what it characteristically does”
(121). With this definition of justice, and speaking in the terms of the city
proposed in the Republic, in order to
understand what justice is in a city (what makes the city perform its functions
well), we need to understand the nature of a city. To highlight the idea of
specific roles (mentioned earlier), Kosman explains that “different folks being
different, they are therefore able to do different things, and there will
therefore be better and worse divisions of labor depending on who does what”
(122). This means that different people have different talents, and in order to
have a society that functions at its best, each person should carry out the
task that he or she does best. Kosman uses the example of popular heist movies,
where many people come together in order to pull off a high stakes robbery that
requires specified roles such as a technician, getaway driver, a computer
specialist, etc. Without each person doing the job that they know best, the
heist wouldn’t be successful (it’s unlikely that the getaway driver could
disarm the alarm systems of whatever institution is being robbed), “for it is
the assignment of tasks according to the principle of giving to each person the
job she is best able to do that results in the condition of justice” (123-124).
So justice, in this sense, is doing the work “for which one is ‘naturally best
suited’” (124).
When dealing with the idea of
justice, Kosman lists a few ideas that need to be kept in mind. The first is
simply to keep in mind that everything Socrates concludes about justice in the
individual is just an analogy of the justice found in his imaginary city.
Kosman warns about this in order to warn against reading the Republic purely from the standpoint of
finding justice within the individual. However, she also warns that “it would
be an equal mistake to read the dialogue as merely an essay in political
imagination” (125). Kosman believes that the Republic has something to do with an intermediate reading between
the two concepts, begging the question “if this is true, we can’t help but
wonder what the relationship is between the justice that characterizes an
individual citizen’s soul and that citizen’s contribution to social and
political justice” (125). Going along with this point, a reading of the Republic shouldn’t entail the search for
a singular definition of justice, virtue, or any other concept, but of the
collaborative definitions of different aspects of those terms that give them
their overall meanings (justice in terms of itself, the individual, a society).
Lastly, Kosman argues that “it is not sufficient to say, as we sometimes do,
that justice according to Plato is a matter of balance or harmony among the
parts of the city or of the individual” but rather the harmony of the whole due to “the differentiation of
function determined by what differentiated parts of the subject are best able
to carry out the subject’s several specific functions” (127).
In this sense, “justice is the
principle of differentiation of function that is based on natural ability”, and since justice is a virtue, “it’s good for
people to do what they’re good at…in a just city, each person practices the
occupation for which he has the
appropriate virtue” (127-128). Going along with this, “justice is the
harmony achieved when each functionally differentiated element of a person is
given and performs a function for which it is best suited, that is, for which
it has the virtue” (128). Recall the overarching issue with Socrates’ argument
in the Republic, where his proposal
dealt with just actions and behavior, while his solution dealt with harmony.
According to the definitions of justice and virtue set forth by Kosman
throughout this article, by individuals differentiating into their respective
virtuous abilities, they will achieve the harmony that Socrates proposed.
Kosman’s argument theoretically effectively resolved the issue with Socrates’
proposed solution.
With this crucial aspect possibly
tying together Socrates’ proposal with his solution, “the Republic may then be seen as an inquiry into the ethics and
metaphysics of difference…the
dialogue thus figures justice as a principle of difference, a principle in
which function is determined by ability and differentiation follows the lines
of virtue” (131). The importance of this solution lies in the ability to
differentiate the parts into their respective roles. Kosman even states that
“one way of thinking of philosophy…is as the ability to understand principles
of sameness and difference” (134). This concept, to Kosman, is key in the sense
that “the Republic’s attention to
justice…is best understood as a principle of appropriate differentiation”
because “no adequate theory of social justice can ignore the issue of how to
accommodate difference and allow for proper and appropriate modes of
distinction” (136). This article, in sum, highlights the importance of the
relationship between justice and virtue and the implications those definitions
have in understanding Socrates’ argument.
1.
With respect to appropriate differentiation,
what if certain individuals didn’t have special function that they could
accomplish, or they were equally inclined to do multiple things at their best?
And what does that mean in terms of the soul and aspects of the self?
2.
What would happen to the overall harmony of an
organization if its individuals lacked certain necessary virtues? Also, along
those lines, what are the (if there are any) required virtues for an entity to
have in order to have the harmony that stems from justice?
3.
One point Kosman was sure to clarify was that
“it’s good for people to do what they’re good at” but that it was another
question on whether or not the people enjoyed what they were good at. If a
person didn’t enjoy what they were good at, how would that effect their
justice, the harmony within their soul, and further their happiness with their
own lives?
4.
With all of the questions above in mind, does
the Republic address different types
of souls, justices? Since differentiation seems to be the key of justice, does
the Republic seem to account for
different types of people and their virtues?
5.
Since the definition of justice is “work
appropriate for one…for which one is ‘naturally best suited’”, would it then be
just to rob a bank, if robbing a bank is what one was ‘naturally best suited’
to do? Is this definition really encompassing for Plato in what it means to be
just?
Question 2: I feel like if an individual lacked any of the virtues, whether it be one or three, there would be no balance. The person would be in disharmony and would not be whole. Each virtue is needed in order for the others to work properly. For example, if wisdom, the calculating part, was no longer present, then the desiring part would do what was not best for them because there is no guidance from the calculating part. One virtue cannot over power another, just like one virtue cannot function properly without another.
ReplyDeleteI think this definition is not complete but it has some truth when applied to a society.Property rights are essential in our society because I would not invest in buying anything if I could not trust that it would not be taken. I also could not do my job if I did not trust that everyone else would do their job. I can be a firefighter and not grow my own food because I trust that Kroger will do this. Kroger doesn't have fire departments because they trust that firefighters will do their job. This creates a harmonious environment with potential for growth. This is an illustration of Justice because good things come from these parts doing their job.
ReplyDeleteQuestion 3: If a person was not happy doing what they were good at, I believe their justice would not be the highest form of justice that Plato/Socrates mentions. It seems that Plato’s form of justice can be regarded as the highest form when applied to the city of necessity. In this city, everyone enjoys doing what they are good at because they are good at it. Initially, Socrates wanted to stay with this city, but was urged to add honors and other aspects, which led to the creation of the feverish city. Therefore, the justice of the feverish city might not be the highest form that Socrates fully supported. Overall, a person that is not enjoying what they are good at still has justice and harmony, but it is not the highest form.
ReplyDeleteQuestion 4: I do not feel like the Republic takes into account different types of souls or different types of justices. Yet with this being said I feel like the Republic is aimed toward building the philosopher class for the purpose of raising the philosopher king. The different types of people are not necessarily the focus or accounted for in the Republic because it seems they aspire to spark change or ignite the path for a new type of leader. Plato seems to be aiming and focusing virtue and justice on a certain type of individual that everyone can learn from but the specifics for other types are not included in the Republic. It seems that the republic is aimed toward a soul that is on the path of happiness and virtue through a more philosophical geared soul to which others can depict what impacts their life or not.
ReplyDeleteQuestion 3: I think if the person didn't enjoy what they were good at this would not be Plato's version of justice. But I'm not sure if this is Plato's point, since he argued against the need for the guardians to be happy, because that was just a part of one person contributing to said person's overall well being (of his soul). But if we look at it at a macro level, that the well being of the city is our goal and it doesn't matter if an individual is happy or not but that he is doing what he's best at, well, this is when I tend to think that Socrates is much more interested in the soul than actually founding a political regime.
ReplyDeleteQuestion 5: I'm glad that I'm not the only one who thought pretty quickly "but what if you're GOOD at doing morally bad things!" Regarding a citizen in the just city, I think this is where the higher capacity must battle lower desire, and rationality (along with the highly regulated educators) will tell the person to channel their skills into something that benefits the state. Our bank robbers end up being of the auxiliaries, able to understand the weak points of entry for the city and training others to counteract those weaknesses... The just in the city is doing your own work, but it's in the mindset that everyone is for the state and used to it. That context can't really be forgotten, or, to some, taken seriously.
ReplyDeleteOf course, it matters more that we draw it back to the soul. The outright definition of justice maintains for the most part, that the three parts of the soul work harmoniously towards a productive end. Our real world bank robber wouldn't be a bank robber, hopefully, because his spiritedness would take his talent for espionage and take it somewhere else, instead of succumbing to the desire to acquire riches. In the city the definition isn't encompassing, but it doesn't need to be. In the soul it is more than encompassing because everyone has a multi-part soul that they can do much with.
I was actually thinking the same thing when I first heard the definition of justice. But I believe that this opens up a question of morals. If we look at justice in Plato's definition, then it would be just for the bank robber to continue doing what he/she is best at. But it doesn't necessarily mean that what he/she is best at is good. For there to be good in the world, there must also be evil. Similarly with justice, there must also be injustice, otherwise there would be no concept of justice. In the soul, the rational part must balance out with the irrational part in order to be considered a healthy soul, meaning that we must have both. I believe the bank robber would play his/her part so that those who are naturally best suited to catching criminals can have a chance to be just in themselves. I think that the definition that Plato gives averts the question of does justice = good? But that's just the way I look at it.
Delete(2) An organization would not run a successful business if everyone is not doing their job. Similarly, Plato states that in order for aa man to have a harmonized soul, each part of the soul must be doing its job and must be good at it. The only time we are good at something is when we truly enjoy doing it. Therefore, when we enjoy our job, we become GOOD at it and when we are good then our soul is harmonized (in order). Thus, according to Plato is the definition of justice. Though this is open for an argument whether a man is good at doing bad things (intentionally) or intentionally good at doing good things. I believe, that's where the education of guardians (or Aristotle's "being constantly at work in the soul") kicks in. If we take the time to learn and feed our soul the right virtues, then we will become just men. Whereas, the other men who are constantly neglecting their soul and feeding into their desires (ex; Money), they will become unjust men. For instance, a group of men crafting an impeccable plan to rob the bank. The group of men went over their plan over and over so, they have now mastered it. It is unquestionable that these group of men is working together- each men doing their job to the best of their ability- to achieve a harmonized job. So, yes they love their job and they are capable of achieving their plan, but it is morally wrong to steal money or anything that does not plan to you. Though these men working together achieving a "harmonized", they lack good virtues. Thus, they lack a harmonized soul and are not just men!
ReplyDelete(3) Plato's constant theme is that if you dedicate your entire self to the city, you will find happiness and satisfaction from simply seeing the city strive and be productive and by doing your part to make this happen. So according to this harmony in your soul would not be based on happiness with your personal job, but instead with knowing that your job is contributing to your city.
ReplyDelete5. I personally believe that the biggest thing to understand with this is while we should do what we are “best suited” we must do what honors virtues. Plato intended virtue to play a part in what we are best suited to do because by doing whatever that is, we will be led to justice. A person may have urges from the desiring part of the soul, but through acting virtuously, we would refrain from those urges. I think Socrates is referring to our virtuous abilities, not what we could be capable of if we acted on the desirous part of the soul. We all have capabilities that could lead to injustice, but justice to Plato is acting on the higher, virtuous way.
ReplyDelete