Tuesday, February 16, 2016

Short Essay 1

Short Essay #1
Jordin Post
2/16/16
A Preliminary Exploration of Defining (In)Justice as Set Forth in Book II

                At the beginning of Book Two, Glaucon takes on Thrasymachus’s argument for injustice being better than justice and fleshes it out to the fullest and richest argument he can make, even if he doesn’t agree with the idea at all. Glaucon throws many things at Socrates, most of which Socrates either combats handily in Book Two or further down the line. The point Socrates manages to ignore—or at least seemingly ignore—is one of the first Glaucon makes: The first definition of justice/injustice. First, Glaucon’s definition is addressed, along with some implications made by the definition. Then I assert (albeit with suspicion) that Socrates only addresses part of what Glaucon’s point made by his definition; what scrap of bone Socrates decides to throw Glaucon and the reader doesn’t seem sufficient. Outlined towards the end are further questions that can stem from this project—worthy of examination, but unable to be put forward as part of research until this issue is resolved.

                Glaucon’s opening argument is scathing, and it all stems from how he originally defines justice. “[Justice] is a mean between what is best—doing injustice without paying the penalty—and what is worst—suffering injustice without being able to avenge oneself” (358e&359a). It is, admittedly, not too far off from anything we saw in book one. What it does differently is defines justice in the context of injustice. Justice is not a virtue as described earlier and later in the Republic. Justice is simply the laws preventing injustice from happening. Glaucon doesn’t go on to define injustice explicitly; all we are provided on that front are examples, such as the story of the Ring of Gyges. Even if we don’t necessarily know what injustice is at this point, Glaucon’s definition ties justice and injustice together, making them dependent on one another.

                The other, subtler part of Glaucon’s definition of justice has to do with what he calls “the genesis and being of justice.” According to Glaucon, people need to “set down a compact among themselves neither to do injustice nor to suffer it” in order to protect themselves. The idea resembles a form of social contract theory. People are giving up their rights to perform injustices in order to form a group of people—I am willing to go so far as to say a city—in order to protect themselves from injustices being enacted on the people in the group. Borrowing a term from Locke and other political theorists, this argument implies a worldview that the state of nature (the baseline of how people act) is unjust and, based off of Glaucon’s examples, fairly violent. There is no specialization that says people who are naturally talented at fighting will commit unjust killings; everyone is unjust, unless they are restrained for convenience.

                It’s no wonder that Socrates initially hesitates to tackle what Glaucon and his brother put up as a defense for injustice! And, yet, the Republic is a testament to that herculean challenge, as he promises to address as much of their arguments as possible to prove that justice itself is worthy and justice unworthy—excluding the benefits of the former while letting the latter have them. Among everything Socrates begins in Book Two (which is quite a bit), Socrates only addresses part of Glaucon’s definition and implications of injustice, and he does it indirectly. Socrates’ decision to make a city as a macroscopic view on justice stems not only from Thrasymachus’ use of cities in book one, but also Glaucon’s definition early in the book. To Socrates, Glaucon has the right idea to pin justice and injustice to the gathering of people. Socrates even puts forth a social contract of his own in his creation of the city analogy, stating “well then… a city, as I believe, comes into being because each of us isn’t self-sufficient but is in need of much” (369b). The choice to make a city is an acknowledgement of Glaucon’s point, as is pinning the genesis of the city to a social contract. When Socrates asks whether or not this genesis of the city is true, Glaucon doesn’t object, even though the wording and intention seem to be different than what he proposed earlier.

                It is Glaucon’s lack of objection or clarification that makes Socrates’ social contract so interesting. Glaucon is not shy when it comes the argument, even at this early stage in the Republic. His easy agreement on this point must mean that either he believes that what Socrates says either sufficiently overpowers what he said previously, agrees with the concept in order to prove it ad absurdum later, or he just trusts that Socrates will take it on later when it is relevant. I am immediately disinclined to believe the last option, as Glaucon rushes and is willing to sidetrack Socrates over points he feels are important and overlooked in several parts of the Republic. Point two doesn’t seem to be true either, as Socrates’ base for the city is something he continues to use as an analogy throughout much of the Republic—for its basic premise to be rendered ad absurdum would dismantle the entire city-soul analogy altogether. The statement itself doesn’t seem to disprove or overpower Glaucon’s point either. If anything, coming together to stave off injustice can be considered part of the very general “much” that people need when they come together to work as a city.

                While Socrates seems to pull many ideas from Glaucon’s argument (even if he doesn’t agree with them), he completely ignores Glaucon’s attempt to make justice and injustice dependent on one another. Before the feverish city is made, Socrates asks Adeimantus “where in [the complete healthy city], then, would justice and injustice be? Along with which of the things we considered did they come into being” (371e). Socrates takes the separation as justice and injustice to be an assumption in his argument, which is again a point that Glaucon does not argue against him for. I will admit to finding no evidence to point at anything Socrates says directly or indirectly pointing out why Glaucon’s assumption isn’t true.

                Having looked at all these angles and not found anything yet from them, I conclude that Socrates doesn’t sufficiently argue against Glaucon’s original point. I put this forward with skepticism, as Plato seems too cunning to include such a definition into Glaucon’s speech and not address it. Perhaps, then, Plato does not have Socrates refute this part of the argument because there is a kernel of truth to it that needs to be explored by the readers. Our interlocutors and Socrates are on the pursuit of justice—to let injustice slip in would be counter to their goal—but it may not be entirely wrong for it to be included.

Word Count without further exploration paths: 1128
Word Count with: 1310

------------------------

Where to take this argument further (in bullets to make things easier!)

·         Regarding Glaucon’s State of Nature (SoN) || Violence in Book 2
o   How the immediate violence of the Ring of Gyges reflects Glaucon’s state of nature argument.
o   How violence plays out in the early city
§  The genesis of war from the feverish city
§  How the spiritedness of the auxiliaries could cause violence (and how it relates to Glaucon’s SoN argument
·         Can Glaucon’s definition of justice in book one be reconciled with Socrates’ definition of justice in book four?
o   It seems that they can, if Glaucon is willing to expand the definition of justice. Justice of the soul means to maintain the parts with harmony. If the state of nature (being unjust) is also the basic nature of the soul, does justice maintain the soul against its basic unjust nature?
·         Why does Plato let some of Glaucon’s points stay without argument?





No comments:

Post a Comment