Farah Rafi
Short Essay 1
The main purpose of the Republic of Plato is to discuss the
argument of why justice is better than injustice. It is interesting that the
first book of the Republic of Plato
can be considered a stand-alone known as the Thrasymachus. Book One offers several different possible
definitions to the concept of justice, such as giving back what one is owed
(331d) and doing good to friends and harm to enemies (332d). But it is the
definition that Thrasymachus gives that haunts the rest of the dialogue, the
one that Plato seems eager to answer and also the most personal. Why is it that
Plato chose the arrogant, hot-headed Thrasymachus to lay to foundation for
Glaucon and Adeimantus to challenge Socrates in the following book? In my
opinion, Thrasymachus is one of the main targets of the argument that
Socrates/Plato makes because he manifests the iniquities of those who are unwilling
to rectify their own ignorance, particularly in the realm of politics, which is
one of the reasons why a philosopher was found guilty of injustice.
When
Thrasymachus presents his argument of justice, his definition remains purely in
the realm of politics. One of Plato’s main reasons for writing the Republic was to determine at what point democracy
becomes so corrupt that a philosopher can be found guilty of injustice.
Thrasymachus is the only one who does not back down from Socrates, instead
choosing to fire with the blank gun that is ignorance rather than admitting
defeat and learning from his mistakes. According to Thrasymachus, justice is
the advantage of the stronger (338c). It can be assumed then that injustice is
the disadvantage of the stronger. This definition identifies a relationship
between the ruler (the stronger) and the citizens by saying that whatever the
ruler wills advantageous, the citizens will be just by following them, essentially
in the form of laws. As Socrates cleverly points out, Thrasymachus failed to
take into account the potentially fallibility of the rulers, stating that
according to this definition, the existence of justice in a citizen depends
solely on the ruler’s ability to discern what is advantageous to him or her
(339c-d). Thrasymachus basically presented two separate forms of justice in
this single definition; one that pertains to the citizens who can be seen as
just by following the laws (the will of the ruler) and another that concerns the
ruler who must know what is in his or her best interests otherwise the citizens
cannot be just. But while Socrates is the one who foiled Thrasymachus’ boldness,
it was Socrates himself that actually succeeded in presenting and defending this very claim in one of
Plato’s earlier dialogues.
The
trial and execution of Socrates no doubt had a big impact on Plato and evidence
can be seen all throughout the Republic.
And in rare cases, Plato can be caught taking from some of his previous
dialogues. The Crito was a dialogue that
presented the question of injustice and whether or not injustice can be used
against itself. In this dialogue, Socrates challenges his friend Crito, who has
come to convince him to escape his execution, to present an argument as to why
his escape from prison would be unjust even though his detainment could be seen
as unjust as well. One of the most remarkable aspects of the dialogue was the
personification of the Laws of Athens, which Socrates uses to make his
argument. He presents what he believes the Laws would say about his potential
escape, stating that it was the Laws that educated and nurtured him from a
young age and that he was free to leave Athens at any time before his arrest
(51d). Ultimately, the Laws ask the question of whether or not it would be just
to disobey the laws even if the laws themselves are unjust (51e). The Laws
never once claimed to be just in themselves, however, disobeying the laws
results in the act of injustice even if the laws are unjust. Doesn’t this
argument sound familiar? This is the flaw that Socrates points out in
Thrasymachus’ definition with the justice of the citizen. Thrasymachus let his
pride get in the way and as a result he lost to Socrates when he pointed out
that a citizen could be unjust even by obeying a law if it is not in the advantage
of the ruler (339d). Had he taken up the voice of the Laws and questioned
whether the act of disobeying a law, even if the law was unjust, would be seen
as injustice, he could have saved his point. Instead he chose to stand by his
argument, claiming that a ruler is only ruler if he or she makes no mistakes
(341a). At least the Laws were not above admitting their faults.
Unlike
the Laws that Socrates personifies in the Crito,
Thrasymachus is not so easily willing to admit that he is mistaken. One of the
main points that Plato emphasizes much in the dialogue is the importance of
education and understanding of philosophy (376b). For him, it is important that
a philosopher be the ruler of the just city as the philosopher is more inclined
to seek truth for itself rather than for the sake of winning an argument, in
other words for selfish reasons. Glaucon and Adeimantus were willing to listen
to Socrates, setting up the challenge to learn from him and to see what he had
to say. This idea of understanding is very important for Plato. For him, the
art of ruling a city justly lies in the heart of philosophy, a ruler with a
love of wisdom. Wisdom, as one of his virtues, is simply the knowledge of what
is beneficial to the city and what is good for the soul(428d). Socrates
essentially took Thrasymachus’ definition of justice, flipped it around and
presented it as the definition of wisdom, with Thrasymachus’ perfect rulers in
the most “precise sense” being translated into the philosopher kings. Instead of
it being the advantage of the stronger, it is the knowledge of what is advantageous to the city. The potential lack of knowledge in the ruler of Thrasymachus’
argument in not knowing what is advantageous to him or her is the hole that
Socrates pokes in the argument and it seems that two books later, he has taken
it upon himself to fix what Thrasymachus was too conceited to acknowledge. This
may have been Socrates’ clever attempt to inform Thrasymachus that he clearly
lacks the wisdom and understanding of what justice is, or wisdom for that
matter.
Thrasymachus
plays a very important role in setting up the rest of the Republic of Plato. Unlike the other definitions of justice
presented in Book 1, Thrasymachus declared the definition of justice as seen in
the realm of politics, one that claimed that justice is whatever is
advantageous to the ruler. It is clear that he lacks the knowledge of what
justice is but more so, rejects the opportunity to understand what the real
justice is. He presents a relationship between ruler and citizens similar to
the Laws in the Crito, where the
justness of a citizen seems to be dependent on obedience to the will of the
ruler/the law of the land. But instead of admitting fault, Thrasymachus attempts
to clarify that his “rulers” are rulers in the most “precise sense”, who lack
fallibility because they are perfect at what they do. Although his dialogue
ends in Book 1, Plato/Socrates does not waste the chance to educate
Thrasymachus by presenting the virtue of wisdom as an inverted version of
Thrasymachus’ definition, adding that it is the knowledge of what is advantageous. It is Thrasymachus’ definition
that Glaucon resurrects and uses to challenge Socrates and it is Thrasymachus
who lacks the will to understand and be educated on justice. It is those who
are like Thrasymachus that are vital targets of Plato’s argument on the
importance of understanding and justice.
No comments:
Post a Comment