Friday, January 22, 2016

Jordan Morris

Summary and Questions on "The Place of the Republic in Plato's Political Thought" by Christopher Rowe

 Throughout Book two of the Republic, Plato describes the arguments of Glaucon and Adeimantus concerning justice. After delving into the two separate theories, Plato uses Socrates to explain justice in terms of the city and to develop his argument of who is best to rule in a city. While the Socrates of Book two emerges as a powerful philosophical figure, one who is a champion of wisdom, it becomes obvious that there is a distinct difference between book 1 and book 2 of Plato’s Republic. What is this cause of this change?

Christopher Rowe offers a key theory in understanding the difference between Book 1 and Book 2 of the Republic, as well as the difference between the Republic and all other Platonic dialogues. Rowe does so by first dividing his efforts into two sections. He first pays attention to other Platonic dialogues while evaluating the role of the statesman and city in politics. He continues to show the stark differences in each dialogue, as well as the role of the Socratic character and his feelings toward the politics throughout Plato’s works. He then turns his attention to the Republic, he and evaluates the influences the Republic and Socrates has had on each and every one of Plato’s works.

At the very beginning of his article, Rowe claims his mission is two fold in proving that, “Socratic conception of philosophy are fundamental to Plato’s political thinking,” and, “the precise relationship between Socrates, the main speaker throughout the Republic, and the philosopher-rulers of the second city he is made by the author to construct” (27). Overall, Rowe’s evaluation proves in fact that Platonic political philosophy has deep centered roots within the Republic that can be traced in all the other Platonic dialogues.

Rowe begins his analysis on Platonic political thought by constructing his first section on the differences between Plato’s other dialogues and the Republic. He points out that perspective is the main difference in each of the other dialogues (29). Rowe claims that the Socratic character is repeatedly emphasized as the only man worthy of ruling over citizens saying, “Socrates is the only one who has, or is as close as anyone comes to having, the kind of expertise that is needed for ruling…he alone has the true interests of his fellow-citizens at heart, and goes about helping them to secure those interests” (29). Socrates is deemed as the true statesman because he is the philosopher.

Rowe points out that these dialogues are meant to examine and explain the political/ruling authorities saying, “all of these dialogues are strongly critical of existing politicians, and have nothing positive to say about their ‘achievements’” (31). Rowe conveys that Plato wanted to offer a model for the type of justice and ruler that was needed, and he concerns himself with explaining the nature of the ideal statesman, which should be knowledgeable, wise, and one that is applicable to the general situations and not specific to each individual. Rowe states that the statesman “cannot be everywhere at once, prescribing individually for everyone…he must do it by setting down general prescriptions” (32).

With this idea of statesmanship in hand, Rowe continues to explain that it is law that helps fulfill the political and statesmanship role in society. Rowe states that the law keeps people acting just and wise even though they are not just and wise themselves (33-34). Rowe continues to show that the subject of the political is extremely important, and that the dialogues represent various aspects of the nature of the political that is deemed necessary. Rowe focuses on the “Socratic dialect” as well as the emphasis of good, which is present in the dialogues in order to serve as a base foundation for the argument of the Republic. To Rowe, the Republic is the union of the pieces present in the dialogues. Rowe finishes his first section of his article by pointing out the differences between the Republic and dialogues will lie within the conclusions instead of the processes (39).

 Rowe begins his second section by evaluating the Republic and its role in Plato’s political discourses. Rowe remarks on the change of the Socratic character and how there is a substantial difference in the dialogues and the Republic. Rowe believes that before the dialogue, the Socratic idea of human good is, “radical and provocative…and all desire is for the good—not for what merely appears or is thought good, but for the real good” (40). He advocates wisdom as the dominant force that will ultimately leads to happiness. Rowe then explains that with this theory, he is able to understand the character and method of Socrates in Plato’s works (40).

There are two particular aspects that he notes that add to the complexity of the Socratic character, one being his focus on “different aspects of the same set of ideas in different dialogues,” and, “that he typically starts from other points of view, other people’s assumptions” (40). Therefore, Rowe points out that these aspects add to confusion as to the conventional method of reasoning of Socrates, or how Socrates illustrates his points in his arguments. Next, Rowe pays attention to the natural difference between book 1 from the rest of the Republic. Rowe states that, “book 2 makes a new start, with Glaucon and Adeimantus restating the case for injustice, and Socrates embarking on a new and apparently more successful search for the nature of justice” (41). While Rowe notes the difference, he believes that Book 1 is still very necessary in understanding Plato’s political thought, and that it resembles the other Platonic dialogues that have been mentioned previously. Rowe believes that there is a newness in present in the Republic after Book 1 saying, “Books 2-10 announce the arrival of a new Plato, writing and thinking in a new way. Book 1, from this perspective, represents a kind of farewell appearance for the od Socrates before he gives way t the new, ambitious constructions that are the mark of the mature (or middle) Plato” (42).

 With this change in mind, Rowe delves deeper into the differences in the Republic, pointing out that the main argument begins from, “the need to convince others of something of which Socrates is himself already convinced and that he himself thinks he has already said enough to show” (43). He then takes us through the illustration of the city in order to find justice and goodness and how philosophers, especially Socrates, are the fitting rulers in a city. After the illustration of the good city, Rowe remarks on another difference between book 1 and the rest of the book. Rowe states that Socrates identifies virtues in book 1, “with wisdom, whereas in Republic 4 wisdom is said to be one thing, and justice, courage, and self-control are said to be other things” (47). This split of virtues, according to Rowe, is a way of elaborating his idea of justice, and finding true personal goodness, while still trying to maintain goodness in those separate virtues Rowe continues to explain the new idea of justice present in the Republic. He speculates that there is a certain system in Plato’s writings that asserted his characters to follow a certain method of reasoning, and therefore, end up with a specific conclusion. Rowe state that now, there is a, “connections between the Platonic idea of justice in the soul and the ‘vulgar’ idea of it” (49).

He continues t examine the differences saying that in book one, “the soul and in everything, it is goodness rather than its badness that enables it to perform its functions well; the function of the soul is ‘taking care and ruling and deliberating and all such things…the goodness of the soul is justice; so the just soul will live well” (51) He explains that this argument is changed by book 4 by explaining, “why the person with a just soul will live better: namely, because the just soul is one in which the reasoning part rules, and the non reasoning parts are rules” (51). With this now explained, Rowe points out that the argument is fulfilled to Glaucon, and he was the one that posed the question back in book 1. Rowe concludes his article by explaining that the ultimate goal in every Platonic dialogue is, “to make people as good as possible” (53), and it is with the argument of justice in the republic that, “will allow him, the position of the Socrates of the pre-Republic dialogues” (53). Therefore, Rowe believes that this argument is key in understanding and the basis for all political thought concerning Plato.

Overall, Rowe believes that Plato makes a substantive change in his writing with the Republic, yet, “retains the basic Socratic view that, as rational beings, it is the real good that we desire, and the real good that it is in all our interests to discover; or else-so Plato adds—to enact, to the highest degree of which we are capable, even if that is divorced from understanding” (53-54).

 1) What does it mean when Rowe refers to the Socratic conception of Philosophy? Is that in line with Plato’s idea of philosophy?

 2) Why is it necessary to understand the other Platonic works? Can the Republic stand on its own feet, or do readers need other support in order to understand Plato’s idea of justice?

3) Why is law viewed so negatively in Platonic dialogues?

4) Is it really necessary for wisdom to be split into different virtues as pointed out on page 47?

 5) Does Rowe make a convincing argument for the need of pre-Republic Dialogues to understand the arguments present in books 1-4 of the Republic?

17 comments:

  1. For question 4: It may not be necessary to split wisdom into different virtues, but it may make it easier. According to Descartes, in order to make firm and constant resolutions, he must "divide each of the difficulties... into as many parts as possible, and as would be required to resolve it better". So maybe wisdom was split up into the different virtues so that they could be analyzed more thoroughly. Maybe you cannot be wise without all the virtues, or maybe you only need most of the virtues. Either way, that is why I feel that it may be easier to split it up, but still not necessary.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Excellent point. There might not be a contradiction between saying in Bk 1 that Justice is Wisdom and saying in Bk 4 that Justice, Wisdom, Courage, and Moderation all exist side by side in the soul. Aristotle will clarify later that Justice can be understood in two ways: as the sum of virtues and as one virtue among others. We seem to be running into this distinction, here.

      The four virtues of book four don't seem to be separate things. Instead, they seem to be four ways of looking at the way the parts of a well-functioning soul interact. Wisdom may not be possible without courage, moderation, and justice. Just as moderation may not be possible without the other three, etc. They seem to be mutually dependent, but it is important for our self-development to be able to think about ourselves in these different ways.

      In this sense, the connection to Descartes is excellent. We break things down into parts not necessarily because those parts are smaller constituents of the things we're interested in, but in order to understand them better.

      I think this is a fine way to think about the interdependence and simultaneous importance of Platonic virtues.

      Delete
  2. Question 3: I do not think that law itself is viewed negatively in Platonic dialogues, but rather the corrupt sort of law that is in control. We see in the Republic that the guardian has to be like the philosopher in order to guard and rule the city. Plato is pushing for the type of law and government that is ruled by those that have knowledge. We also have to remember that laws are only brought up in the Republic because of the development of the feverish city. Ideally, Plato would have liked to keep the city of utmost necessity which does not require laws. Therefore, the negativity that surrounds law in the dialogues arise from there being the wrong type of law in a feverish city.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. That seems right to me, too. Law is a necessary but not sufficient condition for moral development. That's why Socrates wants to stay in Athens (law is necessary), but Athens really needs him (law is insufficient).

      Delete
  3. Question 2: Understanding other Platonic works helps the reader and audience gain a sense of the style and ideals that Plato is trying to convey to the audience. With this being said, I do believe that it is not necessary for understanding Plato's ideal of justice or his writings in the Republic for the majority of the audience. The Republic can stand on its own but maintains the ability to access other platonic work to gain a further in-depth look into specific ideals or conversations. Plato's idea of justice is presented in manner in the Republic that doesn't require other platonic work and gives the audience the definition that fits the conversations and style of the Republic.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. It definitely can. Knowing the other dialogues helps one see what is different about the Republic, and it opens questions about why Plato may have used certain strategies in one place rather than another. But, that doesn't mean that there's not tons of good work to do without making those comparisons.

      Delete
  4. Question 2. I don't think you absolutely have to read other Platonic works to understand the Republic, however; having previously read Plato better prepares you to understand that Plato is not Socrates. Book one and the allegory of the cave in the Republic is not hard to grasp and is thought provoking to a general reader. I think Plato conveys his general ideas clearly but to really understand what Socrates stands for one would have to read other Platonic works. The Republic can stand on its own and it effectively conveys that people should strive to be good and virtuous , and just. To understand that Socrates is not Plato and to understand that Socrates' main concern is the health of the soul one has to read other works.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Exactly right. The Republic is hard. There are all kinds of things that can make it a little easier, and the more serious you are about understanding the Republic, the more interested you get in doing things that will help you understand it. So . . . it's all good in various ways, but not necessarily requisite for a decent reading.

      Delete
  5. Question 4. Rowe refers to a point in which Socrates lumps wisdom and virtue together, and then when wisdom is a virtue separate from the others. Rowe presents two cases as to why this is and I agree with his second one, which seems to point back to the parts of the soul needing to "do their own" as Socrates says. Since Socrates has already divided his city, and divided the people in his city (both healthy and feverish) as one-man-one-job, I think the division of virtue is necessary to keep the city-soul metaphor somewhat clean and connected.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Great point. Look back to my comment on Antony's post to see most of what I have to say about this point, but you add an essential element that I neglected above. In Bk 4, we have a soul broken into parts, so we need an account of justice that takes these parts into account. And, in taking those parts into account, we also get the other virtues. In Bk 1, we don't have a tripartite soul, so that sort of account is not just unnecessary, it is not yet possible. Great point, Jordin.

      Delete
  6. Question 2/question 5: I don't think a knowledge of Platonic dialogues is necessary to read the Republic, but it's definitely an intriguing idea. The author of the paper I reviewed made some assumptions about Socrates' argument using other books written by Plato, and I don't think that this is what Plato intended. Socrates is a character of the dialogues that has similarities with the real Socrates, but I'm not sure if the character Socrates is exactly the same for Plato throughout all of his writings. I'm not completely convinced that the Republic can't stand on it's own, but the point that it is a transition in Platonic thought was a new concept for me that I can't confirm or deny.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. See my comments above. There's plenty of good work to do on the Republic without reference to any other dialogues, and there's some good work that requires such reference. But, the existence of the latter sort of work shouldn't make anyone undervalue the former.

      Delete
  7. For question 3, I don't think law is always necessarily viewed negatively in Platonic dialogues. If "Rowe states that the law keeps people acting just and wise even though they are not just and wise themselves (33-34)" then maybe here the law is a way to create moderation (harmony) in a society where not everyone is perfect, and not everyone will be just (be able to do their respective roles to the best of their ability). Maybe in this light, the law is a way of keeping justice in the real world, in societies where no one person is perfect. The law (properly created) could be a crucial point in Plato's intentions of creating just individuals, by providing imperfect individuals with the means of finding justice within themselves, especially those individuals lacking any virtues or moderation.

    ReplyDelete
  8. Yep. It is important to remember that it was thoroughly conventional in Classical Athens to believe that the role of government was to implement ethical habituation and, thereby, to make people better. Modern conceptions of law sometimes claim that "legislating morality" is legitimate, but also often argue that it isn't. That debate just doesn't seem to be very meaningful to Plato. We need law to make people act right. Then, if they get used to acting right, they may come to understand the value of acting right and choose it freely. We need law to help make us moral, even if law alone can't pull that off.

    ReplyDelete
  9. Excellent work, Jordan, and good questions. You've set this up nicely for anyone interested in the relationship of the Republic to other dialogues, the relationship of Bk 1 to Bk 4, the importance to the argument of dividing the soul into parts, and the role of law in ethical education. Good stuff. Well done.

    ReplyDelete
  10. (2) I think the Republic can stand on its own feet and convey its message effectively. I am going to have to agree with the other guys here in class and go with what they said. Though it will be helpful to read other sources, I don't think it is required to do so in order to understand the Republic. I myself am a first reader of this book and I understand it completely just fine. Though I had trouble understanding Plato's style at first- mainly because I am used to the Socratic style (much more complicated)- as I went on, I found it a lot simpler than Socrates' style. In my own opinion, Plato is straightforward, whereas, Socrates is full of energy and has strategic approach to his conversations.

    ReplyDelete
  11. (2) I do not believe that you need to read Plato's previous works to understand the Republic and his idea of justice. Plato does what I believe to be a great job creating a self contained philosophical work that thoroughly explains his thought process on various topics including justice. The only benefits I would see from reading the other material would be that it would give the reader a better understanding of Plato structures his arguments and give simply for information if desired on these topics.

    ReplyDelete